Beyond utilitarian and fundamentalist approaches to bioethics
problems
Interdisciplinary and pragmatic character of bioethics make
all kinds of radicalism, absolutism and fundamentalism rather unwellcome on its
grounds. However, on the other hand, attitudes waiting around the corner,
gaining much popularity in the present conditions of cultural and ideological
pluralism, ambiguity of all possible authorities and competence assessment,
are-in their very founding design-infected by some contestation of the idea of
moral as a strictly autonomous and unreducible domain. Still, again: these
naturally attractive for bioethics, who is a part of our pluralist, democratic
culture of public life, bear the labels-like pragmatism, utilitarism, discourse
ethics, and even (rarely in a postive sense) relativism-which for the academic
philosophy for philosophy, exercised without any special prospects for
possible applications and without related responsibility are always on edge,
subject to havy criticism. It is, of course, criticism forwarded by these
currents, who identify themeselves and are acctually identified with this what
in philosophy seems to be authoritative through its sens of classic, age and
constitutiveness for what is meant by the word philosophy on the Continent.
The refrain of this multitracked criticism is the argument, that every kind of
pragmatism, either in a form of the rational negotiating theory, or in a form of
some utilitarian account, is an escape from the purely normative, ontically
specific character of a moral situation as such and moral commitment as such,
consisting in reductionism of some kind, reductionism involved in an
old-fashioned fight against windmills of metaphysics.
I share an aversion against post-neopositivist, analitical
and allied resentiments, although I also share a deep disgust with the level of
arumentation proposed by the ideological defenders of the moral principles,
exorcizing the devils of relativism and postmodernists. I also realise how
inefficient classical discources of philosophical ethics, with all their
metaphysical burden, are, when attempts are made to translate them into the
language of legislative practice and to apply them in shaping procedures of the
complex institutions, like these of public health care infrastructure ones.
Nevertheless, so visible and supposedly well-deserved preponderence of those who
support the practical point of view in bioethics does not have to mean any
udeniable authority of the pragmatist doctrine. In a series of articles and
conference papers I have produced in recent years, I tryied to show that the
respect for the ontological instance of the practice, to the how it really
works in life does not need to go always together with the hostility towards
any fundamentalism, ant that the latter leads sometimes to the plainly immoral
effects, when becoming not a guidepost for morality, but selfish, narcistic and
vain dogmatism. This metapermissivism of mine or metatheoretical flexiblity
seem to harmonize with the methodological situation of bioethics, where nobody
is more clever than the others: a philosopher than a doctor, a doctor than a
sociologist, and all together have to observe the requirement that their
contributions have to be understandable for the others and to match somehow to
the overlapping and family unity of the whole discipline.
I can mention here, but of course not develop, three examples,
three themes, in which the proposed attitude of metatheoretical flexibility in
bioethics constitutes itself.
1. The first one is the question of the trust for the
competence of medical and scientific societies in moral issues connected with
their acctivities. The precondition of any rational discussion around these
issues, which is the expertise, being here in doctors and scietists disposal
is unsurpassable. Problems, for instance, of the gene techniques, of the
proceeding with terminally ill persons, of the quasi-aborting operations are in
their major aspects just medical problems and the related practices does not and
cannot match the simlified and naive imaginations of the broad public. In effect
even in courts the decisive advise will be given by medical experts. This
substantial and selfevident authority, sharply limiting all possible ways of
social control over the medical world, imposes on the physicians and the health
care system agents a great responsibility. However, paralely, this unsuspendable
authority constitutes the circumastances which extort a dose of paternalism,
being, after all, another side of the public trust enjoyed (since there cannot
be otherwise) by the doctors. Thus, in this case I defend a kind of
traditionalism and paternalism, turning out as a pragmatic conservatist.
2. The second example is provided by the classical question
of abortion. The way it is often publicly discussed, especially in
theocratically inclined countries, shows how much soulless and cruel the
ideological fundamentalism can be, when it refers to the inviolable moral
principles and imposes at the same time a very restrictive and punitive attitude
towards abortion, irrespective of whether it leads to limitation of this
phenomenon or quite in opposite. It seems to be evident that whenever the
problem of abortion is concerned (like many others in bioethics), the leading
question puting in motion whole discution is: what-to our best knowledge-legal
and institutional solutions might contribute to minimizing a given phenomenon?.
This is a purely pragmatic point of view, however perfectly justified from the
purely moral position, and even more: imperatively commanded as an universal
rule of prudence in a given type of cases.
3. The third example at last. It is provided by the
reflection on the part which the ethicist is supposed to play as a little
authoritatve commentator of the medical life in his country, undergoing the
farreaching reforms and dominated by corrption at the same time. May an ethicist
remain a severe mentor in these circumstances? Shall anyone listen to him or
obey her? Certainly not. And this is exactly for the same reasons which make the
morally overcorrect doctor poves to be unefficacious in the morraly insane
medical society and achieves there less, that it can be a case with someone more
flexibile in moral terms, someone able to undertake a specific moral risk: the
risk of transgression. Here I opt, again like in friendship with pragmatic and
utilitarian tendencies, for some permissivism and moral minimalizm. And again my
motivation is partly metatheoretical: facing the conditions of the true life,
the theory has to show some temperance, if it is to be relevant at all.
|