Bioethics and the Issue of Professional Competence
In the present world, where the sphere of knowledge and
social relations have become extremely complex, the problem of insufficient
competency and inability to manage efficiently the cumulation and distribution
process of various professional skills, has grown very urgent. Paradoxically,
the insufficient knowledge, lacking skill or competence may be advantageous. To
a certain extent, it reduces the threat of arrogant technocracy and meritocracy,
while supporting innovation and creative search process, in which the burden of
excessive erudition has often slowed down progress. Yet, obviously, the
uncontrolled incompetence is dangerous in general, and particularly in all those
cases when incompetent persons are entrusted with extensive responsibility and
authority.
In general, two distinct forms of incompetence exist. The
former one is a self-controlled incompetence, enlightened with the Socratic
awareness: I do know that I know nothing. The latter, is an
uncontrolled and uncontrollable incompetency, which shows no sign of
self-awareness. To the contrary, it is convinced of exceptional erudition and
ability.
Similarly to all other complex and science-related fields of
social life, in medicine and health care incompetency is very common,
and-understandably-very hazardous. The dramatic status of this problem in
medical practice is underlined by the fact that the social function of medical
doctor relies strongly on social confidence: particularly in the less affluent
and tradition-oriented nations. More or less justifiably, doctors and medical
officials generally believe that all cases of acknowledged incompetence, errors
and insufficient skill cases tend to undermine such social confidence. It is
true that the self-critical declaration of incompetence may lead to positive
impression only in the most culturally advanced and educated societies. In
typical societies, i. e. poor and uneducated, if such declarations are made at
all, they result usually of the opportunist reasons, i. e. as justification
necessary to avoid responsibility for given patient or bureaucratic difficulties
and pass it over to others.
I would like to indicate here some of those areas where the
issue of incompetence does appear in medicine and health care, i. e. those areas
where the improvement of incompetence management mechanisms is necessary in
order to anticipate and neutralise possible negative effects. Besides, I mean to
point out an interplay between two stages of the competence/incompetence
complex-the professional and the moral ones.
The primary area where both the insufficient competence, and
inability to acknowledge it, emerge in the field of medical education, i. e.
medical studies, hospital internships, medical specialisation, and academic
career. The huge scope of contemporary medical knowledge results in the
situation when it is absolutely impossible for medical universities to provide
students with anything more than general introduction to medicine. Yet, those
academic institutions are still pervaded with the conviction about allegedly
professional knowledge inculcated into every general practitioner or specialist
doctor. However, the structure of obtained knowledge is typically amateur,
though supported by everyday practice and vocational experience relying on
intuition rather than profound knowledge. That is why the training of physicians
should gain a lot by applying extensively the methods used in amateur education,
or popular practical instruction, rather than upholding the non-realistic and
conceited ethos proclaiming the professionalism of every medical doctor.
Paradoxically, the educational techniques applied in popular courses emphasise
the self-awareness of incompetency, and the readiness to search for knowledge in
reference books, to a much greater extent than classical academic education. The
half-professional character of medical practice in poor countries leads to the
situation when doctors are reluctant to learn anything at all, despite news on
drugs, and draw their knowledge exclusively from the instruction leaflets
accompanying newly developed pharmaceuticals. The illusion of scientifically
sound knowledge wielded by doctors has been reinforced by the behaviour of
academic scientists: In fierce competition for available financial grants, they
have grown extremely reluctant to acknowledge incompetency or research failures.
Paralely the pressure grows to mask and deny negative research results, which
leads at best to the information chaos and missleading optimism in many areas of
medicine. Thus, an extremely poor example is given to emulate by rank-and-file
practitioners.
Health care management has been another area breeding
insufficient competence and related hazards. In poor countries, the plight of
health care system has been made more dramatic by the fact that -due to overall
corruption-the awareness of the relative separateness of managerial and medical
expertise fields has been obliterated or marginalised. In result, physicians,
usually those of inferior stature, who were unable to pursue purely medical or
academic career, manage almost all health care units.
The above mentioned areas of medical life necessarily rely on
a certain moral and normative order. Also this moral sphere requires a definite
level of competence. Such competence is based on the awareness of certain moral
imperatives, the knowledge of specific obligations and liabilities expected from
the medical and administrative staff. Yet, the level of moral awareness
prevailing in the medicine practised in poor countries is generally very low. In
fact, it is practically reduced to the conviction that certain regulations exist
which ought to be followed if possible, and it is morally correct to
follow them, in general; occasionally, there may appear exceptionally complex
situations causing conscience dilemmas. In such rare situations the voice of
individual conscience or religious convictions may matter. Yet, this sphere is
considered entirely private and excluded from public scrutiny. The atrophy of
elementary moral language and total neglect of moral standards related to
medical vocation, lead to desperate corruption and demoralisation of
professional relations. Unfortunately, this demoralisation has been reinforced
by the unlimited authority, or even cult of medical doctors, typical for poor
nations, which have been exposed to powerful processes of modernist
secularisation producing as a side-effect a phenomenon of medical doctors
increasingly assuming the social stature of traditional clergy.
The moral sphere, more distinctively than the
technical-professional one, unveils mechanisms and the true sense of the
comeptence partition and dispersion. On the simpliest level we see quite
commonly how in everyday diagnostic and therapeutic practicies, involving
medical knowledge, the responsibility for a patient is being shifted by doctors
to other doctors as well as to the technical diagnostic processes that can be
continued pratically endlessly. In other words, a difficult patient is often
thrown over to another place, possibly far from my own office-to the
specialist in other field, to the higher rank specialist in my field, to another
lab for new tests. This way of conduct is basically always formally
correct-from both, professional and moral, points of view-since expression of
carefulness and uncertainty, like we have to check also this or we need to
exclude also that possibility seem to pass for a measure of professional
honesty. However, such a competent incompetence, ambigious expression of the
responsibility on the one hand and, perhaps, of avoiding difficulties and
circumstances that may unveil our ignorance on the other, obviously has its
morally frustrating aspects. It comes out just of this vague and slow dispersion
of responsibility and slips down to a sort of generalisation and
depersonalisation of responsibility for a patient in a technocratic, totalist
and proud world of the medical practice and knowledge that develops in the
countries under modernisation. If a strictly professional competence is usually
in this or that way quantifiable or divisible, then, on the contrary, the moral
competency, the virtue, just dies through partition. Dies together with any
responsibility that may exceed anyhow the legal understanding of this term. Of
course, no social mechanism of avoiding individual responsibility for a
patients fate does not really neutralise this responsibility, but instead of
this, it undermins and puts into doubts moral competency of medical societies.
It refers specially to some poorer countries, where all sorts of problems, also
moral ones, can pass for explained when related to the shortage of money,
reforms or to the bad system functioning. In opposition to the
technical-professional expertise, which when acknowledged, sometimes can even
contribute to the doctors prestige, any open declaration of moral
incompetency socially compromises the given individual and seem hardly possible.
We do sometimes confess sins, however we never say: I regret very much, but I
have not sufficient moral faculty in order to bear responsibility for my
profesional practice to the expected extent. This quite essential metaethical
condition turns out to be a major obstacle for the moral improvement of the
medical societies and the sad consequence of this state of the matter is that in
this moraly loose atmosphere also the typycally professional-technical
incompetences become less and less discernable as causing any moral disorder.
Whats more, this is just the method of a competent incompetence-a proud way
of declaring ones lack of a special knowledge of some kind-which allows us to
avoid direct responsibility and more: to avoid any moral burden, any
questionability of ones conduct. We come then to the deplorable conclusion that
at least in the less developed countries the scietific and technical progress of
medicine not only supports dispersion of responsibility for a patient, but
destroys public sense of the moral among medical professionals, corrupts the
sense of the special moral vunerability of medical practicies.
|