Ethics, Eugenics, Genetics
The new genetic techniques stimulate the minds of the public
to visions of the future. Scientists, dealing with the matter as a question of
routine competences and practicality, refuse to share the general excitement,
even claiming this excitement to be a sign of ignorance which should be avoided
in all cases. Consequently, the serious consideration of the possible long term
results of applying the new techniques is being halt-officially
excluded from academic discussion and remains a matter of literature, public
discussion and other instances of quite problematic authority. Philosophers
then have a duty to take the risk of being considered too ignorant, too vague,
or at least unjustified in their conclusions, but nevertheless of speaking for
the public and creating an intermediate space of discourse joining specialists
and nonspecialists. Such a space does not exist up
to now, at least in the academic arena, making the consideration of all possible
issues of the development of gene techniques a matter either for scientific
expertise or (at best) for journalism.
Certainly, the authority of a scientist, who has the best
reasons not to mythologize what is a question of
pure technique and reason, should not be undermined, and I would say even more:
this authority must be protected against populistic
hysteria and unjustified political claims to the power of control and assessment.
However, we must not forget the limits to
scientific competence and get overwhelmed by light-minded
scientism, shifting moral challenges of all kinds into the guardianship
of religion and public moral supervision, whoevers
responsibility that might be.
The question of imagination-not scientific
anticipation, not fantasy, but just imagination-of possible material
consequences of the development of genetic techniques is not the only one which
must be carefully taken into account. This is only a challenge for our
imaginative skills: let us present to our minds what may really happen when the
human genotype becomes to any significant extent
manipulable. How much more serious is the consequent challenge to our
moral condition and sense of responsibility! For what we must now face is the
question of how to develop our moral concepts and skills in order to meet
the coming future technical reality with responsibility. This does not mean: how
can we preserve our values exactly as they are, and protect ourselves against
immoral changes by controlling scientific developments? It is quite
irrelevant and irresponsible to think that long term restrictions can be imposed
upon scientific experiments and that all possible moral turbulences can in that
way be prevented from occurring at all. Not only is it true that the sciences
are free and powerful in their independent development, but it is also true that
those who are able only to speak about restrictions, means of control and
preserving the status quo are not able to maintain their moral authority
when changes turn out to be unavoidable.
I will try to sketch what may be called threats (what I
prefer to call challenges). We must take the risk of and responsibility for
imagining what may be unavoidable in the next century-the eugenic society. The
subject-taboo after World War II-must be re-established as a topic for ethical
consideration. We must try to find out how democratic societies can produce the
new moral power to carry out, for instance, new limitations of freedom-the
limitation of procreation and damage to ones health, etc. We must try to
imagine what moral powers we must take on in order to cope with the possible
loss of evidence by such categories as parenthood, brotherhood, gender, race and
even the ontological individuality of the human
being. The presentation aims to contribute to the new and necessary academic
behaviour: deliberating on what is impossible and unknown now, but imaginable
in the future and therefore requiring careful consideration rather than derision.
The entire moral effort undertaken by mankind in the current
phase of its existence (which is
proKiblv but an initial stage) has focused on
regulating the relations between self-reliant and
egotically organised human individuals. The central ethical motif may be
defined as the endeavour to overcome the natural egoism shown by beings to whom
the self had been assigned. Human beings have been serving this assignment,
and indeed have been enslaved by it, in all moments of their existence. This
motif determined the entire history of social custom, morality, law and
political order. It is a very essence of human nature that individuals
invariably promote their particular selves: while pursuing the path of pleasure,
or striving for virtue and salvation. The great moral hope of mankind relies on
conviction that the prevalent ethical order assures the condition where the
ultimate individual objectives and values are not concurrent to the final good
of entire human community. This fundamental postulate had been formulated in the
West by the Stoics and combines all moral cultures of the world. It is our faith
and our ethical norm. We cherish the conviction that human beings had been
called to reason and moral nobility (virtue). Thus humans are called to reject
low egoism, and at least to reconcile their good and objectives with the good
and objectives of other people. It is only on the margin of mainstream ethics
that suggestions were formulated seeing moral progress in reduction of
individualistic claims. Such proposals, which were rare and vigorously opposed,
assumed the predominance of collective entities (mankind or state) over the
individual personal good. Having experienced the 20th century totalitarianism,
we are ready to reject such suggestions as finally compromised.
Though, today we are facing an entirely new perspective of
disin-dividualisation in mankind existence. In
effect, we face the challenge of partial change of
egological principle of ethical conduct. It is not a Utopian programme of
political revolution that we face but a rather more real perspective of
technological revolution. Hence, a part of mankind may be covered by protective
umbrella of technologies enabling such control over body that obliterates the
limits of individual bodily identity and making the dramatic
radicality of death far more fuzzy. A human
individual who is able to plan a clone reconstruction of sick tissues and organs,
and who can expect a far-reaching regeneration of his own tissues or adaptation
of transplants, must necessarily formulate a different attitude to bodily
identity and mortality. If
we supplement the image of future situation with the already
emerging possibilities of global information network, providing much deeper
possibilities of participation in public sphere, we can anticipate the model of
human being much less concerned existentially with
his/her individual self, less neurotic and indeed stronger, through some measure
of liberation from servdom to his own ego and fear
about his being and well-being. Hopefully, this new society will not consist of
egoists laboriously building the higer moral and
public reality by elimination of the primitive conflict of interests and
considering reconciliation as a main spiritual creative force. If this
optimistic hope were realised, the community life would gain a new sustained
value. No longer will it be but a superstructure or emanation of the individual
lives of the multitude of humans.
We have not yet faced all the problems. It is necessary to
confront another imaginable concept which is both realistic and horrible. It is
in the framework of this terrifying image that we must find the value of good,
which is overshadowed by the fear we experience. This image relates to the
intervention of law and technology in human reproduction process. In
consequence, we shall face restrictions to freedom which do not exist nowadays
even in the dictatorial states. Let us not cherish any illusions that this great
sphere of freedom, the sphere of free procreation, shall remain outside the
control of human law and institutions. Since the technological instruments of
such control have been developed and demographical
issue has become urgent, we should assume that such control shall be instituted.
It must be expected also that the anti-racist, or indeed anti-eugenic paradigms
related to 20th century idiosyncrasies, shall be gradually eliminated in future.
The potential advantages resulting of the possibility to prevent the emergence
of defective foetuses and the birth of disabled creatures, and the possibility
of promoting favourable genetic features are so prevalent that no moral
principles can dissuade humanity from applying such technologies. The acts of
sterilisation and abortion, which are currently subject to powerful social myths,
will be probably insignificant in the future eugenic procedures.
If we are to face this challenge successfully, we must be
able to look at human life beyond the particular heroic morality of building
common good on the foundation of individual egoisms,
beyond purely idividualist ethics of purely
individualised human beings. If we undertake such attempt, it will appear that
such formulations as: human being is most important, human life is the
highest value, everyone has the right to live, may be ultimately treated as
formulas securing the egoistic interests of persons who need such safeguards
to declare their contribution in construction of non-egoist common good.
The human individual partially relieved of the fear of death,
and having a certain perspective of bodily continuation of his good components,
to be continued in organisms being his off-springs generated in various ways:
from genetically controlled procreation, through survival in transplanted organs,
organic regeneration, up to clonic
reconstruction-such human individual will more credibly represent not only
himself or herself, but will also be a true member of community assuming
communal responsibility. Though it is hardly imaginable, the future man may have
the feeling that he/she is the bearer of both good and evil properties-both in
biological and moral sense-and not all of them deserve continuation. It
is painful for us to imagine such situation because we are firmly attached to
our currently existing nature and we are ready to defend to the bitter
end the ethics of compromise between private egoism and the sublime general
moral ideals. If we were asked whether there exists a legitimate
authority determining what elements in humans are good (and should be continued)
while other elements are evil (and should be eliminated) we should visualise
probably some individual justice deciding authocratically
about life and death. Though, the decision-making organ of eugenic valuation
need not be discretional or dictatorial. In essence, the entire social life can
be seen as a great system of evaluation of good and evil, and the realisation of
such assessment effects. The eugenic state may be as just or unjust, as
free or dictatorial, as repressive or non-repressive as
pre-eugenic state in which we live now.
It is our responsibility to exercise the imagination and
possibly anticipate the moral, political and cultural situation faced by mankind
when the technologies of control over physical body are sufficiently developed.
Our present futurology will possibly prove to be naive, but that is no
sufficient reason to abandon such studies. We must
try to foresee the future problems. The responsibility for future
development is the only element which will prove significant for our
grandchildren and successors, even if we are able to give them little cues to
problems that we can only envisage, while future
generations will face them as hard reality.
Let us imagine then an eugenic society (state), where the
following conditions apply:
1. the full genotype (or the knowledge about elementary
biological terms) of each human individual is conditionally available to state
organs (or institutions successor to national state);
2. technological possibilities exist for far-reaching
modification of genotype, control of procreation, differentiation and mutation
of various tissue cells, entire organs, and entire human organisms;
3. the concept of sex becomes fuzzy and partially separated
from the image of role division in procreation;
4. procreation is not entirely discretional and is not the
only method of generation of human beings;
5. the concepts of kinship, and in particular fatherhood,
matern-inty and sister/brotherhood are essentially
reconfigurated or supplemented with terms related
to the level of genetic homogeneity between two persons, age difference (in
relation to relatively determined moments of life
initiation or new life initiation) and the currently indicated gender;
6. the individual resources of experience, life history, and
all elements currently belonging to individual sphere, being absolutely
personal and unrepeatable, is partially submitted to
transcorporalisation;
7. the social position is partially dependent on biological
assessment of individual being;
8. humanity is divided into many tribes or
genetical races revealing incremental differences
and accepts many competing concepts of racial perfection;
9. eugenic societies coexist with traditional societies (states).
No one is prepared to consider such atrocious possibilities. That is why such
images seem terrifying. However, our imagination cannot be released of even such
demanding tasks. Such profoundly disturbing and
emotionally loaded hypotheses
are best tackled analytically
when answering the
questions about the possible realisation of basic values in the hypothesised
conditions. In what way can such values as freedom, justice, love be present in
the eugenic society?
No particular causes can be identified why the eugenic
society could not be free and democratic. On the contrary, the presently
unimaginable pluralism of the society including essentially different beings:
naturally born humans, the cloned humans, the in vitro genetically
constructed humans and genetically engineered individuals, for instance
ape-slaves, seems to favour the development of elastic and relatively liberal
legislation. Pluralism usually leads to more political liberty than it is the
case in homogeneous societies. The effective legal order and justice are not
essentially contradictory to the complex nature of eugenic society. The
opposite may be true: the extremely complicated relations, resulting of the
biological nature of social divisions and rivalry, may result in the
construction of efficient legal mechanisms. This conclusion can be drawn on the
historical example of the United States where the multiracial nature of the
society was the cornerstone of the very high legal standards.
Yet, it is well imaginable that the eugenic society will be a
difficult venture, pervaded with conflicts and antagonisms. The racial and
biological differences between humans have invariably resulted in mutual
isolation and competition between social groups. The
strenghtening of such differences will most probably emphasise such
alienation phenomena. What is more, the extension of state power over biological
procreation and reproduction leads naturally to conflicts. Similarly to all
licencing systems, the discretional element cannot be eliminated by fully
rational procedures and criteria.
It is also very challenging to face the perspective of
coexistence between eugenic societies (technologically and biologically
superior) and the traditional societies, unwilling or unable to control their
genetic stream and biological resources. When facing the demographic defeat,
eugenic societies may feel tempted to impose on entire mankind central standards
of genetic and reproduction control. Non-conformance
to such standards might be considered as a sort of aggression: the
accu-multaion of chaotic demographic potential (biological
and genetical), difficult to contain in territorial and
bio-topological aspects.
In particular, I do not see any reasons for optimism shown by
many contemporary humanists who believe that the developed
lib eral democratic societies will be able to avert
war forever. Emphatically, it seems that the partial
disindividualisation of human being, the partial
fuzzying of death, relativisation of human
body integrity, and all other elements possibly resulting of the manipulation of
human genetic stream, will result in significant inflation of individual life
value, which may in consequence lead to increased warmongering. Such new
generation wars may be more demographically
devastating than ever before.
In the ultimate existential dimension, each human society
experiences difficult life, bearing the burden of disillusionment and tragic
fate. In the eugenic society, the human species qualities will be partially
subject to human engineering. Though, the human fate shall not be free of
contingency and tragic essence, defining the mortal and imperfect life of human
being.
The modern epoch, with its great ideals of civil liberty and
national sovereignty, equality and law-obedience, conceived as principles of
state, political diverties and democratic liberty,
has been fading into history. It is not true that the present day condition is
the point to which humanity has endeavoured. It is not true that we are at the
end of history, and all the following events shall be post-historical. Indeed,
we face a very difficult process of revising and correcting the political and
moral ideals, which have prevailed since the time of the French Revolution. This
process is a great challenge consisting of partial tasks related to definite
walks of life. Each of those areas should be addressed earnestly. It is ours-the
philosophers-responsibility to devote all our attention and intelligence to
this task, refuting the facille revulsion or
philisterism revealed in narrow-mindedness, which
attempts to see the future in the narrow terms of the present. One of the major
constituent challenges relates to the techniques of control over the body.
|