Illness as evil and illness as good
It is bad to be ill. Illness is
pain-a cardinal form of evil, together with weakness,
sin, wrongdoing, and disgrace.
Among all the forms of evil it is perhaps illness
which most directly and urgently calls for action. This action-treatment-is good
and as such it confers its own value upon everything
that makes it possible. In the light of this
understanding of good, illness itself acquires a secondary,
indirect, yet nonetheless real value: in other words illness is also good. In
the language of classical metaphysics, factors like this are referred to as
transcendental good: a type of good inherent by default in even the most
wretched constituents of our essentially good (as it is God's creation) world. I
will not, however, attempt to claim these metaphysical heights. On the contrary,
I will confine myself to a pragmatic methodological perspective.
My paper, as the title suggests, will be devoted to the
ambiguity apparent in reactions to and opinions about illness. I will present an
axiological dialectic whose
dynamism provides grounds for the dynamism of the human practice of treating
diseases. Similarly, stimulating ambiguities and dialectics are encountered in
the area of crime and its prevention as well a.s in
the complex relationship between individual egos and state institutions that
enforce action orientated towards a common goal. In all these cases, an initial
evil becomes a condition for the emergence of a highly developed product of
culture, be it the science of medicine and health care, or the legal system, or
democratic institutions.
I will not attempt to present a systematic analysis of the
theoretical and practical problems in the area described in the title. All I
would like to do is to show how the aforementioned axiological ambiguity comes
to the fore in different, more or less theoretical notions of illness and
treatment, as well as in popular beliefs. In order
to accept those points of view which see illness as good, a departure from the
classical concept of good is needed.
Namely, I am asking you to put
aside that concept located at the crossroads of general metaphysics and
practical philosophy and defined in the following way: good is
whatever is the direct
or indirect goal of action. in particular of human action. The concept
of good that I have in mind is perhaps
equally classical but. somehow mysteriously, competing with the former,
namely: good in
whatever contains, creates, or enhances an enriching meaning - which leads
towards perfection.
There are numerous phrases that describe the decline from
perfect health (to death) and accentuate different
kinds and aspects of such a decline: some of them express the philosophy of
the speaker as well as describing
the illness.
Here is a list of some words and phrases
that describe this decline, together
with explanations of their meaning: I) Pain-bad,
negative physical or psychological
sensation; 2) Weakness-feebleness,
lack of vital powers; 3) Poor health-a general
condition of the body. being prone to disease; 4) Ailment-a slight but
persistent malfunction of an organ or organs; 5) Disease-an impairment of
normal physiological
function, a pathological change: we refer to this
situation by saying simply: I am ill; 6) Hurt, injury, wound-a sudden and
serious malfunction, a break in the structure and violation of the integrity of
the organs, even persistent damage to a part of the body; 7) Disability-a
persistent handicap, malfunction or lack of an
essential organ(s), seriously
affecting one's everyday life; either inborn or resulting from a disease or
accident; 8) Monstrosity-a marked structural deformity of an organ; 9) Symptom-any
unusual sensation or change in bodily functions (something's happened to me); 10) Syndrome-a
theoretical medical notion describing a well-defined set of phenomena and
processes conceived of as bad for an organism.
We have some of these bad things in mind when we utter the
word illness or disease in various contexts. The relevant semantic field is
further broadened by different beliefs and ideas of
what really happens inside us when we are ill-in any of the above meanings.
These beliefs and ideas can be quite simple, or can amount to entire medical
theories, but all of them are grounded in general beliefs about what illness is
in general and what its particular types consist in. This popular ideology and
typology of illness seems to be worth analysing; not the least interesting is
the fact that the categories of diseases are defined by certain cardinal
diseases and diseases as cultural symbols:
leprosy and syphilis, for instance.
1. The most primitive belief is, of course, the mythological
idea of illness as being possessed by evil forces. The idea of mental disease
as possession by the devil and of infectious disease as bad air both conform
to this paradigm, as well as the explanation of illness as a punishment sent by
God. These all are versions of the myth of disease as the intervention of an
external super-human power, an intervention that is caused either by an
infringement of a taboo, or as a result of sin.
Illness in this sense is always accompanied by moral taint, a disgrace on the ill. Its
symbols are the
leper and the lunatic.
2. Another classical view of illness, or at least of one of
its essential types. is the idea of disequilibrium,
of upsetting the balance of certain regulative components of the body-blood, phlegm, yellow bile. and
black bile. for instance. A paradigmatic disease in this sense is sickness or
intoxication. The notion of illness as a disequilibrium and disharmony turned
out to be exceptionally fruitful for the science of medicine. It was this concept that enabled the change from treatment in the form of exorcism to
treatment in the form of detoxification by applying a specially prepared
substance: a remedy. This concept paved the way for modern pharmacology.
3. A medical topos of bad blood
links the early modern concept of illness as an alchemical violation of
homeostasis with the concept of illness as partial
death: decay, rot, or gangrene. The prominent diseases here are the vapours
and syphilis. Treatment consists mostly in purification of the body: surgical
removal of decayed parts, amputations, cutting ulcers open,
letting blood. >From the desire to remove all
rotten bodily matter arose the most military of all medical disciplines-modern
surgery. A sort of medical conservatism is also grounded in the same concept,
namely, an approach that considers many diseases as relatively natural phenomena,
similar to aging. and thus, unworthy of intensive treatment.
4. Yet another modern view of pathology-the mechanistic
one-is symbolised by paralysis. Disease is a fault in the bodily mechanism-a
malfunction. Something has gotten stuck, a cyclic process has been
interrupted, a circuit has been cut, a vein has been blocked. The idea has
proven to be extremely important for scientific medicine, since it emphasises
the phenomena of conductivity, metabolism, and circulation. The search for a
motor of the bodily mechanism directed the efforts of medicine toward studying
the functions of the heart. This spiritual supremacy of cardiology is still
prevalent in contemporary medicine-and certainly the fact that cardiac arrest is
the most common cause of death is not the sole reason for it.
5. The most awesome disease of all-cancer-symbolises another
type of illness: illness consisting in turning the
vital powers of the body against itself (illness as a tumour, growth,
monstrosity). In this category illness can be described as self-aggression,
self-destruction, and anarchy in an organism. Neoplasms,
acromegalies, and allergies-understood as auto-aggression of the body-are
paradigm cases of diseases that support the idea that the ultimate cause of
illness is the patient himself.
Having surveyed, though all too briefly,
the morphology of the evil of illness, keeping in
mind the whole network of various had associations
aroused by the word illness, we are now
in a position to recognise
their mirror images in the concepts and ideas
through which illness manifests itself as a
non-evil, and indeed,
as something positive and in a sense good. The existence of this positive reflex
is inevitable for pragmatic reasons. Since illness
is the necessary prerequisite for the existence of therapy and medicine. it must be tamed,
accepted and explained by those who live with
disease and those who live off it-by patients and
doctors. Like every inevitable thing. illness must be presented
as something meaningful and valuable in the broad perspective
of the human condition.
All philosophical theories of illness, maybe except pessimistically existentialist
philosophies, strive to discover a sense in illness.
The Christian concept of illness is ambiguous in this respect. Learned
Christianity, on the one hand. teaches that illness
is a trial through which God tests our faith. Illness is, moreover, a
memento mori-a figure of death, and a path to
death. It therefore has a significant religious dimension; it is one of the ways
to God. an opportunity for penance for the sinner, an opportunity for conversion
for the infidel, and generally an opportunity for diverting thoughts from
everyday mundane tasks to matters connected with salvation of the soul. On the other hand, however, popular Christianity tends to see
illness mostly as something bad that God allows to exist-therefore it has to be
borne, and accepted. Sometimes illness is even seen as God's just punishment,
implying that whoever is ill must have deserved it.
The classical Greek concept of illness is most manifest in
the stoic heritage. In this tradition, illness appears to be insignificant.
The virtuous man ignores it, or, more precisely, accepts it as a fact of life
towards which his attitude should be one of indifference. Illness does not
encroach onto the sphere of his spiritual autonomy. Undergoing treatment is
perhaps advisable, but only in so far as it is advisable to exploit all
favourable opportunities -but without excessive effort to bring them about. From
this point of view illness is not so much an evil as an obstruction.
Doctors of antiquity knew how to treat many diseases quite
well, and scientific medicine existed in the late Middle Ages too (mostly thanks
to Avicenna). but it was not until modern times
that the idea of an active fight against disease came into being. We owe its
birth to the modern spirit in philosophy. But not entirely and not everywhere.
For the modern spirit in philosophy was far from homogeneous, and could be divided-provisionally-into two
intellectual trends: a naturalist, positivist one
and-in contradistinction-a spiritualist and
romantic one. It was the former one-evolving from
lAth-ccntury medical alchemy to positivisi
somatism. symbolised
by the cult of anatomy and vivisection,
that inspired the search for active methods of
remedial treatment. Illness was becoming more and
more axio-logically neutral: a natural, though unwelcome, stale of
an organism, as natural as all
other diversions from norms which abound in nature. From this perspective health
is a norm. whereas illness is an abnormality. On the other hand. romantic
modernity is responsible for the aesthete concept of illness (we will come
back to it later), as well as for the revival of spiritualist magical practices.
These were dominant in the Renaissance, and today they resound in
several-sometimes moving, despite their naivety-descriptions of efforts of a
seriously ill person to regain health as if they were
heroic battles with a cunning enemy who nevertheless can always be repelled with
spiritual strength and an indestructible will to live.
Philosophies, or rather ideologies, of illness influenced not
only general concepts of medicine, but also the practical attitudes of doctors
as well. A conservative doctor with Christian or classical attitudes is by no
means quick to opt for active and aggressive treatment. Illness for him is a
natural state and most diseases, as he is always ready to remind us, are
self-curable. Moreover, every age has its diseases, and the biological clock
cannot be out-maneuvered. When the time comes for dying, for arteriosclerosis, a
stroke, or cancer, the patient should be allowed to die quietly. Intensive
treatment is only justified in cases where minor diseases turn into serious ones,
or when a dangerous disease occurs unjustly-the patient is too young and too
healthy for it. It should be said that such traditionalists among doctors are
rather rare today. The active type is dominating-and not only because modern
ethics demands that the doctor do everything possible for the patient,
but also due to the fact that in a contemporary free-market society, doctors -like
everyone else (including philosophers!)-tend to sell their services as broadly
as possible. An active doctor, thus, treats you even when you are as fit as a
fiddle; for example, he/she may recommend prophylactic treatment, or a diet and
a healthy way of life; or he/she may prescribe vitamins, cosmetics, and
Prozac (if you happen to live in the US). If you
feel just a bit under the weather-and have made the mistake of telling him/her about it-he/she will come up with the most
sophisticated treatment. Nobody is allowed to be ill in his/her presence-let
alone die. In the world of active medicine, the boundaries between illness and
health, prevention and therapy, serious disease and hypochondria, have been
obliterated. This is perhaps why allergy seems to be the favourite of
contemporary medicine.
As we have seen, in the complex
history of medical beliefs and ideas. illness was
looked upon not only as a definite evil but also as a
manifestation of the natural (and supernatural) order of things, as something irrelevant
and trivial but also as something significant and
important. Human activities oriented towards the tight against diseases were.
and still are. being amplified by the forces inherent in tensions between
various ideas, concepts, beliefs. and opinions connected with diseases and treating
them. It is not worth talking too much about the fact that it is bad to be ill. It seems, however. worthwhile to point to another extreme in the
whole range of opinions that have ever occurred in the philosophy of illness. This is the aesthete approach that has already
been mentioned, the idea that illness has certain
specific inherent moral and aesthetic values.
The aesthetics of illness is
grounded in a prima facie justified belief that the
socio-psychological type of an individual is partially determined by his/her
physical appearance: the way he or she looks, his/her age. the condition of the
body. The unique personal quality of an individual is thus often co-determined
by certain flaws, imperfections, and disabilities. It is hard to be a noble
Nestor without being aged: a justified user of a walking stick must suffer from
at least a slight impediment of movement, etc. The
Romantic movement valued the aesthetic aspect of illness to an extent that
provoked some to pretend to be ill (e.g., by using pale powders) and even
to engender it artificially (e.g., by drinking acetic acid). Romantic ideals
emphasized connections between the hapless life of an artist and the content and
quality of his creation. A persistent and unbearable disease often figured
prominently among the necessary calamities of a respectable artist. Thus illness
was perceived as both a manifestation of and the reason for the artist's
sublime sensitivity. Moreover, it guaranteed the truth of his creation. Great
patients in the history of culture include Marcus
Aurelius, Pascal, Nietzsche, and Proust. Among diseases allegedly
connected with high spiritual values, tuberculosis and various heart problems
can be mentioned, along with-even more significantly-all diseases perceived as
specific to upper social classes, such as haemophilia, migraine, and anemia. The
commoners, who were also not incapable of appreciating the value of illness, had
to content themselves with illnesses which had socially initiating value and symbolised transition to the next class in a
hierarchy defined by age (generation). Such illness of age included first the
diseases of childhood, then diseases of middle-age-going bald and putting on weight (if we may count these as
quasi-diseases), and finally diseases of old age.
There can be no doubt that a world without diseases would not
be a human world: neither would a world without senility and dying. This is
ultimately why doctors
will always remain suspect individuals who tend to intervene in the natural
order of things in this best of all possible worlds.
|