Ontological analysis of the ill-being
Was auf ein natürliches Leben beschränkt ist, vermag durch
sich selbst nicht über sein unmittelbares Dasein hinausgehen; aber es wird durch
ein Anderes darüber hinausgetrieben, und dies Hinausgerissenwerden ist sein Tod.
G.W.F. Hegel, Phänomenologie
des Geistes
Philosophers word on the forum of the medical humanities is
not always welcome. The tangible reality of suffering seems to be something
sacred to the extent that excludes the play of speculation from its domain.
Indeed, very much the same thing has been thought very often about Godly things.
Therefore, I was happy to have presented the following few speculative ideas (although
quite Kierkegaardian, and therefore somewhat anti-speculative at the same time)
initially in the town which was the birthplace of the man who had enough courage
to say (against theologians) that "there is nothing more excellent than
philosophizing" and that "only philosphers are wise men." These are words of the
arguably the greatest mind of Linkoping and Sweden as a whole, of the Boetius of
Sweden.
In my presentation I intend to sketch a few dialectical
moments constituting the existential nature of the living, resp. organic entity,
in so far as this entity is human. For the man to be a living being is to have
body. The split into natural and spiritual ways of being in man, and the
character of our unity overcoming this split-the unity relying upon the
intentional creations of culture: words, concepts, ideas-determines our
corporality as alienated and meaningfull at the same time. Since we are not
capable any more of being in the Nature, our way of being in it, after
all, is the way of ill-being. Being not of this world, we are permanently ill.
This is our "nature"-the sanity, the health is nothing more than "forgotten
illness," precisely as in Nietzsches aphorism on truth: as we remember, for
Nietzsche, the truth is nothing but a forgotten metaphor.
The point of departure of my reasoning is the statement that
the ill-being is not a peculiar state of a living body, but rather the
ontological, substantial determination of the living organism-specifically of
the human organism-whose existence consists in living-towards-death-that is, in
illness.
Naturally, there is nothing new in undermining the simplified
opposition of the health as the natural state of organism and the illness as its
violation. Let us take for granted the basic issue of the constructionists
analysis that makes us perceive illness as a socially and linguistically
constructed entity, related to the judgments, expectations, ideals and needs of
man. If a man and/or a women are partly spiritual beings, then their ways of
being healthy or ill are also creations of the spirit or culture. Without
denying that health and illness are concepts of the living human culture, which
should be considered within the antropology, I would add that both these
concepts surely have also their purely ontological meanings related to the
organic fundament of the spiritual life of man. These meanings are opposed to
the cultural ones in so far as human attempts to overcome Nature are an effort
to oppose Nature. And the nature is neither healthy nor disordered in itself; it
is rather that both these aspects remain complementary features of Life as such.
Only as a cultural being, is man healthy or ill. And exactly: as a cultural
being, man is an ill-being; his overcoming of Nature, his consciousness are
precisely what make him/her ontologically an ill-being. Ill-being is not meant
here in the antropological sense of the eternal unhappiness or in the sense of
the "unhappy consciousness" of some kind, but in the ontological sense of
internalizing in ourselves the painfull opposition of the nature and the spirit.
We are ill-beings-this means that we suffer not only as spiritual creatures, but
also as natural entities. We are degenerated, alienated not from Nature
as such, but from our very nature, from the nature of our own being. We
are ill-beings as internally contradictory entities, whose identity is always
and only postulated, intended, apparent. Our efforts to maintain our sense of
individuality and, subsequently, our actual identity, are hopeless tasks-this is
so since we must die before we attain this goal. And it is precisely because of
this, that our suffering is so real. Its reality is just a negative, the other
side of the intentional, artefactual way of being-and it can aggravate even the
worst diseases. We must die as humans. We die, we surrender, for Culture must
surrender to Nature. We perhaps win our spiritual eternality when ascending up
from the common all too practical intersubjecive culture (do we really?), but at
the same time we lose our lives. A being of culture cannot sustain itself in the
confrontation with pure Nature. Neither is it able to sustain its own identity
in the confrontation with the upper world of the spirit which incorporates that
which is extra-temporarily valid in us: the truth we seize, the virtue we
acquire. Man is mortal because man is a historical and a cultural being; as a
cultural being he is a mortal-being; as such he is also an ill-being. Animals
are not. And therefore they never really die, they are never really ill. Their
death, their suffering is just the way nature goes, the course of changing forms,
the movement which is Life itself.
But the order of tangible reality makes itself apparent again.
Should we at all speculate about what is the question of the painfully personal
experience-the suffering of the ill person? Besides, what may be more organic in
nature than a disease? What may be more real in human life? Do not we say: let
us only stay healthy? I feel that I must explain myself once more.
Well, we should acknowledge that we are organisms, organic
beings, irrespective of the fact whether we would like to claim that our life
cannot be wholly reduced to the life of an organism, or not. If so, then who are
we as organisms?, what is the existential nature of the organism? Is an
individual organism an autothelic substance, maintaining itself throughout its
own activity, i. e. living substance? Not at all. There exists only one
stream of life, one substance of Organic Life. The separate entities-cells,
organisms, species-are only relatively and temporarily independent parts of it.
The idea of a body, of a body being a subject or being an aspect of the "I"
pertains only to Man. This is an anthropological idea. When we genuinely suffer,
that means that it is we, as bodies, that suffer. And this does not mean that we
suffer as the genuine elements of Nature; just the opposite: this means that we
suffer as Bodily Entities, which assumes: as Cultural Beings. Through
postulating the idea of the body within our own life and on the public stage of
our intellectual culture, we set in motion the struggle for ourselves, for our
identity which is always to be belived and claimed for, and never to be
experienced. Human intentional body is a struggling body. But we do
genuinely have our bodies. Our intentional, culture-made body is real-it is
exactly this featherless, vertical, slim, degenerated body. We are always doomed
to suffer the soreness of our body, for we are ill-beings. Our body is of this
world, althought we, women and men, are not of this world! Therefore the life of
our contradictory bodies-at the same time physical and intentional ("culture-made")
bodies-means the permanent struggle for maintaining itself. The body lives in a
way which relies on permanent ensuring its own coherence and substantiality in
the course of the permanent effort. What we ascribe willingly to the
organism-that it is a whole constantly defending its own integrity-concerns only
human body. The animal, the organism does not "want to live"-it just lives, just
continues to go on, together with Nature. It never dies for real, since the
nature, the very substance of animal life subsists continuously. Animals are
eternal in the nature like humans are eternal in the spirit.
Having the body, suffering the illness, awaiting the
death-these are typical aspects of the human way of existence. When reffering to
animals we can use these terms, but only in an analogous sense. Originally,
these terms are mediated in the sphere of human intentionality and self-creation,
as parts of the socially elaborated self-understanding of man, as parts of his
"natural antropology." This makes the concepts of body, illness, death,
ambiguous and illusoric in a way. At least as far as they report the
consciousness of failure dominating in human culture whenever it discovers (and
it discovers it everyday) that culture and its transitory, temporal creatures,
as such only imitate what is the true home of man, the purely spiritual world.
In other words: the very concept of illness symbolises the failure immanent to
human life, to human culture-the failure in attaining the goal of our vocation
and the failure in subsisting as a part of Nature.
Thus, a body lives through having its own negativity in
itself. As an impossible idea of something spiritual within Nature, the body as
such is ill. Its inherent negativity, its internal contradiction is illness.
The resolution of this contradiction, the end of every impossible
body, the end of its ill-being is death. Death, therefore, is a negative
telos of a body and the very essence of bodys existence is its
living-towards-death. This way of living, the (very own) life of a body is
precisely an illness. Thus, mortality means being always on the way to
death, being always ill. The ontology of the ill-being is the ontology of the
mortal-being.
These metaphysical remarks have their consequences also for
medical concepts. The illness as it is commonly understood, i. e. in a sense of
a more or less sudden event, emerging from the basic state of "health" seems to
be nothing but the accidental symptom of the permanent,
existentially-grounded illness of a body which is a way of being of any human
living entity. It means that every occasional illness as such is "symptomatic,"
as a superficial appearance of the Illness of human being as such. The regard on
that fact annuls subsequently the distinction between causal and symptomatic
therapy. The treatment is revealing the state of the common, average ill-being (called
"health") and it this sense this activity is loyal to the regular everyday
course of self-realisation of the body, to its tendency to die subsequently to a
kind of continual and regular process of decline. This means solidarity with the
general ill-being against occasional illness: let us die later and more
peacefully. However, from the point of view of our real vocation and necessary
failure of our efforts to make it true within the temporal, natural scope of our
life, the very sense of any treatment is quite dubious. Does a longer life, free
of pain, bring us closer to our goals? Does it make us wiser, better or at least
more happy? This is very doubtful indeed.
The same dialectical ambiguity concerns also the difference
between nature (naturalness) and pathology. If "natural" means satisfying
statistically justified expectations, then typical, normal-pathology would mean
untypical, unusual. In a sense of a core medical knowledge, pathology, would
make something domesticated, usual of something previously unknown and unusual.
Therefore, along with the proposed definition, any therapy would contradict
itself-illness would become natural to it (isnt it quite a wise thing for a
doctor to say: "it is natural for humans to be sometimes ill"?). For illnesses,
all of them, are statistically natural; they are also natural in terms of
something being ultimately accepted by God (if you prefer this way of conceiving
the concept of nature). The same with death. And who would dare to improve
nature (or God)!?! Of course, this dialectics is quite common in the practice of
treatment: when facing "natural being ill" or "natural death" of old people,
medicine keeps much more quite and passive, than in a case of "unjust,"
"unnatural" pathology and death of young people. Perhaps then the practice tends
towards another concept of pathology, more subjective, namely as something bad,
painful which is as such unexpected, unaccepted or even unjust, and claims for
our counterreaction. This is obviously a moral determination, reffering to the
cultural and not only organic human life. Moreover it is untranslatable into the
language of physiology. But we should not complain about that. Involving
suffering, emotions and moral ideas into the determination of pathology is in
harmony with the essence of the matter itself. For illness is intrinsic to the
core of human life, to the ontological essence of Man: the ill-being.
Originaly, illness is the phenomenon of the intelligence, or,
to put it more strictly: of the self-consciousness. Psychic pain, knowledge of
the self as an ill-being, unhappy with that what he or she has and experiences
is a precondition of illness. It is more crucial and essential point that we
might suppose considering only the remark that man suffers consciously and the
self-knowledge of illness belongs to its very phenomenon. For this truth has
also its deeper aspect: any full objectivisation of pathology, grasping it in
the physiological terms and-as purely descriptive-forfeiting any valuation,
completely loses any sense of evil involved in suffering. On the other
hand-which is not less important-we face the same lack of understanding and
compassion when taking the above, purely idealistic position. Namely, from the
point of view of principles of human being and his vocation, the whole corporal
life of man is going to be absolutely subordinated to the sovereign power of the
rational human being, who is as such completely free of any suffering and any
other form of dependence of Nature. This is just the stoic point of view. This
vanishing of the true concept of suffering and illness on two poles-naturalistic
and purely spiritual-confirms only that the human ill-being belongs to the
transitive and artefactual sphere of being-in-culture.
The essential difference grasped in the popular opposition of
the health and the illness seems to rely upon the circumstances in which
the body tends towards the resolution which is its death: functional or mechanic
disorganisation, as well as infection or intoxication, especially if they make
us suffer or if they shorten our life-these are "illnesses" and "diseases."
However, in any case, it is our cultural determination that we tend to think
that it is better for us to live longer than shorter. This principle-which is
the prime motive of the whole medical science-has no rational justification and
this very fact makes medicine a very ambigious kind of human activity. There
seems to be no essential difference between prolonging ones life for ten years
or ten hours. For the Nature itself, it is wholly indifferent how long we
live-if you die, someone will replace you. On the other hand, our ideal vocation
is neither to live longer nor to suffer less. Our vocatiion is to acquire the
truth and virtue, then-to enter the eternal world. So simple as it is, since
Renaissance we got unable to treat this truth seriously. This is our madness and
ultimate confirmation of our modern ill-being.
|