The Definition of Mental Disorder and Discourse Strategies in
Psychiatry
Please consider certain elements of my contribution to
conference discussion as confidential, since my subject: the control of public
discourse in the field of psychiatry is sensitive. Yet, my opinions reflect the
approach of a philosopher rather than a medical specialist in psychiatry. In
effect, the postulated confidentiality can only be considered a rhetorical
device at the plan of fiction rather than reality.
My short introduction to the study of this broad and
important problem must be preceded by a certain methodological declaration. I
venture the ongoing opinions in my capacity of philosopher and rely on the
principles of bioethics, which is one of the study fields in philosophy. It is
my conviction that the specific mission of bioethics lies in the fact that its
objectives are defined in the following way: (1) identification of bridge roads
between advanced philosophical concepts and practical issues linked to the human
individuals relation to his/her body and natural environment; (2) the
facilitation of mutual contacts between the groups of specialists (e. g. medical
doctors) and the broad population deprived of the specialist insights (e. g. the
patients). In brief, I consider bioethics a practical philosophical mission
contributing to social welfare. Since as philosopher I am involved every day in
highly speculative and abstract concepts, it is in this field that I am trying
to redeem my utter impracticality, by strong pragmatism in approach to
bio-ethical issues which are close to my heart.
Let me offer another methodological reservation. The field of
psychiatry-understood broadly as a comprehensive social, legal and institutional
entity-is both the border area and model study object of bioethics. It belongs
to the border zone, since the psychiatric practice is essentially not involved
with physical body, while its moral dimension exceeds the sphere of usual
problems arising in biomedical ethics. It is a model object-since the dramatic
issue if incompatibility and conflict between the professional expertise of
physicians and the expectations of broad public, so frequently encountered in
medicine, becomes particularly sensitive in psychiatry: perhaps even more so
than it is the case in attitudes to euthanasia or abortion.
Clinical psychiatry-for many historic and methodological
reasons needs permanent self-defence and self-legitimisation, even in relation
to the medical environment. Politics is the public mode of psychiatrys
existence. In relation to broad public, psychiatry must cope with the burden of
historical disrepute castigating it as a field of abominable coercion, while in
contacts with other medical scholars, psychiatrists are permanently suspected of
deficiencies in strictly medical aspect, i. e. the somatic therapeutics. Yet,
psychiatry has been most oppressed recently by legislation and leftist
politicians. The suspicions and groundless claims for control powers by
politicians and officers have been so pervasive that numerous psychiatrists
succumbed to indoctrination. These doctors have developed symptoms of
self-suspicion and even co-operate with judicial officers pestering psychiatric
wards.
In this ideologically oppressive situation, where clinical
psychiatry currently stands in the West, the psychiatrists are compelled to
undertake defensive measures. They have to pursue active policy aiming at the
promotion of their social standing and overall legitimisation. Yet, it must not
be understood as opportunism in relation to fears and prejudices surrounding
psychiatry. In my discussion over the definition of mental disorder offered next,
I systematically relate to this issue-the defence strategy of clinical
psychiatry and the possible ways of using the definition topos.
Let me formulate a final methodological remark. Definition
cannot be considered the ultimate objective of knowledge, while the construction
of definition is no proof of the authors expertise. The definition is used in
motivation and concentration of cognitive activities, the testing of obtained
results (applied as a test of conceptual efficiency), but first of all
definition has a practical applicability as criterion formulation allowing to
classify objects belonging to given categories.
In the case of psychiatry the definition problem is neither
essentially cognitive in nature nor indeed intensely desired by psychiatrists
themselves. On the other hand, it is a key point in the strategy of those
politicians and lawyers who wish to subject psychiatric wards to overwhelming
control in the name of the protection of patients rights. It follows that
clinical psychiatrists do not particularly look forward to the dubious practical
benefits resulting of the strict criterion-based definition of mental disorder.
Most often, even an utter non-specialist is able to identify a person with
mental problems without recourse to any definitions; the mentally troubled
person is usually different from all other individuals, being a queer type or
a lunatic. Basically, psychiatrists need the definition of mental disorder as
a defensive measure against the unfriendly political trends, while the lawyer
looks forward to such definition that would facilitate him the intervention in
psychiatric cases. Thus, the issue is more political than cognitive in nature.
Alas, the rules of the game require that the psychiatrists don the cap of
uninterested scholar and present his motives as purely scientific. At this
point, the philosopher comes handy, since he is allowed to proclaim openly what
the psychiatrist will never do, i. e. to declare that the issue is essentially
political rather than scientific. And this is precisely what I am saying. In
further analysis, I shall attempt to identify the difficulties that occur in the
formulation of definition strategy that could be of some benefit for psychiatry
and provide it with a certain measure of immunity against the incessant
political claims.
The general public consists of individuals who are
instinctively fearful of mental disorders, fear mentally troubled persons, are
afraid of psychiatrists, and-last but not least- are ashamed of their own fears
and prejudice. Consequently they are willing to accept all sophisms undermining
the real existence of mental disorders in general. Thus, for the sake of this
audience it is necessary to adopt the attitude full of understanding and
appeasement of possible fears. This is the key to my proposal: mental disorders
should be defined in the way that allays fears and reflects the understanding of
the social reception of the phenomenon of psychic illness. Yet, it must not mean
the embracing of opportunism and joining those who implicitly deny the very
existence of mental disorders. Such resignation may be alluring but is obviously
destructive for psychiatry.
Michel Foucaults famous study Madness and Civilisation
emphasises the definition problem. In eighteenth century, at the beginning
stage of psychiatry, mental troubles were defined as the disorder of moral and
intellectual abilities, accompanied by bodily disorders. Thus, the illness was
defined through the categories of deficiency: deficiency of reason, deficiency
of virtue, or the lack of organic harmony. The illness was considered as
illusion, since the nonsense and deprivation of reason apparent in madness, were
but deviations from the road of reality towards the wild moors of illusion. In
Foucaults opinion madness in classicism was not interpreted as a definite
change in the mind or body. Rather it was conditioned by nonsense expression
accompanied by bodily deficiency or unusual behaviour and mode of speech.
Classicist concept of madness is directly and most generally reflected in the
word delirium. This word is the derivative of lira, the route.
Thus deliro means exactly the deviation from beaten track, from the
straight road of reason. The tendency to repulse the illness as such and to
eliminate it from consciousness is clearly visible in these classicist
propositions. Of course the patient was expected to adopt the same repulsive
attitude towards his illness. The classicist recipe might be formulated along
the following lines: if the patient herself were in position to react correctly,
she would be the severest judge of her own madness. Indeed it would be in the
patients interest to support even the cruellest forms of combating the illness.
This argument was used to legitimise the coercion and social exclusion which
were the hallmarks of pre-modern approach to mental ailments. An essential
change in definition strategy occurred in modern times. The
moral-intellectual-somatic approaches was succeeded by the emotional-somatic
concept. Until very recently the broad categorisation prevailed which
differentiated between mental disorders in strict sense, which were treated as
forms of neurosis, i. e. emotional troubles reflected in the somatic condition,
and profound psychoses the origins of which were sought in somatic states, e. g.
neurological causes. The fissure between the psychological and somatic approach
to psychiatric diagnostics and therapy has remained very evident. In spite of
this essential change and the modern predominance of morally neutral categories
pertaining to emotions, personality or individual character, i. e. the incursion
of emotions psychology in the psychiatry sphere, the old element of repulsion
has been subtly preserved: the possessed of pre-modern times, the captives of
evil powers, subject to moral decay at the moral and intellectual plan, appear
now to have been enslaved by another internal power-emotions and imagination.
Thus modern concepts have preserved the ambiguous sense of delusion which had
always been used in definition of madness. The galley rowers of imagination
are the luckless and internally enslaved individuals enslaved by the powers
of imagination and irrevocable personality decay, sinking in non-being, which is
the very essence of their illness. Antoni
Kêpiñskis psychiatry is wrought with a profound philosophical dilemma: how it
is possible to reconcile the concept of illness as essential acute evil and
obvious suffering, with the concept of mental disorder as a special
condition offering specific high human values. The core of this dilemma can be
seen as contradiction between the repulsion of the evil brought by illness,
understood classically-as delusion or madness, and, on the other hand, the
denial of illness resulting of the identification of some positive values in
illness, certain good which cannot be reconciled with illness as absolute
evil.
It is my opinion that within the assumed definition strategy
we must beware the line of thought which makes the illness unreal (which is a
classic approach, though strengthened in modern times by the popularity of so
called anti-psychiatry and reality therapy), and the repulsion concept. Mental
disorder must be understood as real and profound evil, though treatment cannot
be reduced to a simple intervention aiming at the elimination of evil from the
patients soul. Rather, the therapy ought to assist the patient in the internal
process, in which he himself struggles with his suffering. It seems that most
modern psychiatrists understand their task along very similar lines. Thus, my
further strategic remarks may prove realistic. I am going to present them in
following numbered paragraphs:
1. The current socially accepted discourse explaining the
mental illness relies on positivist motives and leftist political sensitiveness.
It is said that psychoses are health disorders-implicitly similar to other
health problems. Everyone may experience such troubles. It is further implied
that they have basically organic causes and can be reduced to the category of
ailments with somatic aetiology. Moreover, it is understood that a subtle
relation or neighbourhood exists between psychoses and neuroses, i. e. emotional
troubles with recurrent fear conditions, which to some extent are experienced by
a significant share of population. The pro-social ideology would supplement this
line of discourse with the observation about social sources of mental disorders,
i. e. implicit social guilt, which a conscious society must assume. In
consequence, the mentally deranged should be approached with understanding and
assisted if possible. Yet, this strategy may have double effect: it provides
psychiatry with a measure of public legitimisation, but, simultaneously,
justifies the incursion of state and non-governmental organisations in their
efforts to control psychiatric wards.
2. In my opinion, the discourse strategy outlined in section
1 required appropriate modification, which would safeguard the sovereignty of
medical authority against the unjustified control incursions. It is recommended
to replace the fear-based topos: everyone may suffer a mental condition
with the dialectic formulation no one is absolutely mentally sound-but everyone
can expect expert psychiatric care when needed. In order to allay the social
fears and repulsion in relation to mental troubles, public discourse ought to
link closely psychotic conditions with other-more acceptable mental
troubles-such as neuroses, mental retardation or dementia. Thus, a certain moral
shield shall be provided to psychotics. It is commendable to promote a broad
concept embracing all health disorders having their source or significant
component in mental conditions. The re-introduction of the concept of soul would
be very helpful. The soul is currently nearly tantamount to psyche
but in moral dimension it is much more meaningful. In effect, it would be
possible to define a category of ailments corresponding to psychiatric cases as
soul conditions.
3. The positivist and naturalist ideological under-structure
used to boost the psychiatrys scientific authority by proposing that the
essence of psychiatry lies in medical treatment targeted at the somatic sources
of psychiatric cases makes the applied discourse unconvincing. Maybe it would be
advantageous for psychiatrists to aim at an independent status-different from
medical doctors and psychologists, rather than to cling desperately to the title
of medical doctors, first and foremost. Neither the medical area, nor the field
of social welfare institutions, is very hospitable to psychiatrists, who
experience to some extent the symptom of social exclusion suffered by their
patients. I am inclined to recommend the discourse of representative/curator,
which has developed in some parts of the world already. The psychiatrist is the
patients representative and curator, or ombudsman helping him/her to survive
and representing his/her interests in contacts with hostile social environment.
The formal adoption of such role by psychiatrists provides a barrier and
de-legitimisation to administrative control incursions and boosts the
psychiatrists status as the main principal reference group in the field of
legislation concerning mental problems.
4. Considering the fact that majority of politicians voting
in parliaments have no knowledge of mental disorders and psychiatry, it is
commendable to promote the topos allaying the emotions of fear. According
to my fragmentary knowledge, in the first order of importance it is necessary to
explain why and when physical coercion is used in psychiatric wards (i. e. more
frequently in cases of the patients exhaustion caused by mania rather
than the cases of violent fury); when the hospitalisation is enforced (the
enforcement being relative and gradual); the nature of electroshock therapy. It
must be explained that chemical coercion, i. e. the application of strong
sedatives, is by far more widespread in psychiatry than physical enforcement of
behaviour. In effect, the gravity point of disputes concerning psychiatric
practice may migrate from the area of enforced hospitalisation and the patients
rights towards more professional discussions concerning the application rules
and scope of pharmacological therapy. When the discussion in centred on these
issues, the psychiatrists may regain the dominant position in public discourse,
since few laymen are prepared to question their expertise in the application of
drugs and their effects. In consequence of higher public standing, psychiatrists
in particular countries will be able to secure more control over legislation
process in matters pertaining to psychiatry. They will also have more to say in
the solution of key issues such as conditions of enforced hospitalisation, and
sensitive problems including the psychiatric aspects of approach to multiple
murderers.
The discourse strategy in every intellectual field focuses
all its basic issues in definition procedures. Therefore, I shall next attempt
to translate the above-proposed directives into definition construction with
respect to the phenomenon of mental disorder.
The objective of the definition of mental disorder proposed
by psychiatrists ought to be essentially moral and promotional. The definition
should aim to boost the low moral standing of the patients, protect them against
aggression and-what is equally important-support the political status of
psychiatrists. In effect, psychiatrists will have more say in legislative
process related to mental care, and will find it easier to find finance sources
for research and treatment. Yet, the definition ought to be scientifically sound
and introduce structural order at the current level of knowledge.
I suggest the following defining terms. According to the
postulate suggested earlier, I rely originally on the concept of spiritual
ailments in general, and proceed to specify the mental illness: the spiritual (soul)
disorder is a complex of acute or chronic difficulties encountered by individual
in independent survival under standard social conditions, including the
institutions of general social welfare and in spite of the overall satisfactory
physical condition, while:
- the difficulty is understood as complete inability or
deficiency of will and everyday activities resulting in their ineffectiveness or
purposelessness, or accompanied by obvious suffering, and
- survival is understood as physical survival not
accompanied by permanent hazard of health collapse or legally significant
conflict with the environment.
In relation to the general category of spiritual disorders,
the psychoses are defined as a subcategory thereof. Mental disorders are seen as
such spiritual ailments where, permanently or temporarily, the patients
consciousness of illness and critical reason is impaired or non-existent, in
spite of the overall satisfactory level of intelligence.
The proposed definition terms are purely pragmatic and remain
to some degree relative in relation to social and legal conditions. The
suggested terms pertain to behavioural aspects, while explicitly avoiding to
rely on any existing psychiatric theory. In result, the definition is expected
to be stable and effective in building public consensus with respect to
contentious social issues related to the psychiatric system. The applied terms
emphasise the suffering and the necessity to assist the mentally troubled humans
while strengthening and supporting the psychiatrists authority. The problem of
mental disorder is approached both as inherently medical and social issue, thus
fitting very well in the mainstream discourse of socialisation. In effect,
psychiatrists are supplied with a good defensive tool in the same area, which
has been traditionally the launch pad of threats to their sovereignty and
authority. Yet, the law ideology drawing from social-democratic (resp.
liberal-in American terminology) policies in relation to psychiatry is but a
form of socialisation discourse.
The political quality of proposed definition strategy is
advantageous for psychiatry, and, consequently, is beneficial to patients.
Similarly to other fields of bioethics, we encounter in the case of psychiatric
ethics the problem of disproportion between the knowledge held by a narrow group
of experts and relative ignorance of wide publics. Also similarly to other
bio-ethical fields, that approach to arising issues is most rational which
respects the expertise of the knowledgeable professional group. Such was the
intention of suggestions and formulations offered in my paper.
|